John O. Campbell
August 2016
Richard Dawkins famously observed that [1]:
however
many ways there may be of being alive, it is certain that there are vastly more
ways of being dead
This truism may well be extended to existence in general:
however many ways there may be to exist, it is certain that there are vastly
more ways to not exist. The world of existence appears to be only sparsely
populated from the possibilities. For example, the 100-odd atomic elements
which do have an existence are greatly outnumbered by the infinite number of
possible combinations of protons and neutrons. The laws of nature ordain that
the forces of attraction between most of these combinations are unable to overcome
the forces of repulsion and it is only those few combinations where the forces
of attraction dominate which may have an existence.
Existence
Science has very little to say about existence or about how
phenomena come into existence. Some physicists have speculated on how
something, in the form of a fundamental physical entity, was able to emerge
from the primal vacuum, to transform from non-existence into existence. But
this misses the important point that fundamental physics is only a small part
of the larger story. What about the existence of complex phenomena such as
occur in human culture? Although some physicists have named the anticipated
theory the ‘theory of everything’ it will only explain existence at the most
fundamental level, such theories hold no hope of explaining more complex
phenomena. We are led to conclude that the existence of more complex systems
may only be explained through an understanding of the evolution of complex
phenomena from less complex forms. Such a general theory should explain both
how phenomena comes into existence and how phenomena are maintained within
existence.
Understanding how new complex forms come into existence is especially
difficult as these are historical events which have left little direct
evidence. Consensus on detailed explanations of the major transitions, such as
from chemistry to biology or from biology to culture, are lacking even in their
general principles.
In thinking that a ‘final’ theory is within their grasp,
physicists may have grossly underestimated the subtleties of nature. Vast
realms of unexplored reality containing possible structures lurk at a scale
below our ability to detect. Phenomena down to a scale of about 10-15
meters are currently amenable to experimental probes but the arena of space-time
may extend down to the Planck scale at 10-34 meters. We are largely ignorant of the phenomena
within this vast unexplored arena.
Already some theories speculate on possible entities such as
graphs and preons at smaller scales. Complementary to a theory explaining the how
entities at the most fundamental scale come into existence would be a theory
that explained how such entities evolved into more complex forms. As we will
see below there are good reasons to suggest that a single evolutionary logic
operates at all scales and across many subject matters.
Existence is the subject of the main branch of philosophy,
Metaphysics. The earliest western philosophers focused on discerning the basic
substance composing existence; earth, vapors and water were early contenders.
Aristotle thought there might be four: air, earth, fire and water. Later some,
such as Charles Saunders Peirce, would brilliantly philosophize on the nature
of existence [2]. Needless to say,
many definitions have been suggested in both science and philosophy.
The definition I will work with is the one suggested by
Wikipedia [3]:
Existence is commonly held to be that
which objectively persists independent of one's presence
This definition has
some strong points and a weak one. First the strong ones:
A weak aspect of this definition is that it may suggest that
objective existence is described by science in a somewhat anthropomorphic
manner. It may imply that something exists only when science can confirm its
existence. We should be clear that scientific existence is not just another
explanation for existence, science aspires to describe existing phenomena as it
is, it strives to describe an actual ‘true’ reality despite being constrained
by the fact that it is a cultural project.- Existence requires persistence. An existing phenomenon must persist, it must remain intact and retain its identity over some period of time. In more complex systems, such as biological ones, this aspect of existence is called homeostasis but we should recognize that even fundamental entities such as electrons must also maintain their identity.
- Existence is objective. This is often interpreted to mean that existing phenomena must be indicated by reproducible evidence and that existence is therefore described by science.
In this paradigm all aspects of reality, not just
scientists, are objective observers and existent objective phenomena must
appear the same in their interactions with all aspects of reality. There must
be a consensus on what exists and this consensus includes the experience of
electrons just as much as the experience of scientists.
Underlying the objective aspects of existence is the fact
that phenomena may only exist if they are able to affect other entities in
reality. This may be made clearer if we imagine, on the contrary, some entity
that is incapable of interacting with anything else. In that case it could not
be experienced by anything else and it could have no effect on anything else. Thus,
it could not be said to exist in the wider reality.
Existence and Evolution
Scientific understanding of the history of the universe
since its beginning in the big bang reveals an evolutionary history. In the
very beginning there was only massless radiation. More complex fundamental
particles including those having mass emerged in sequence from simple to more
complex. This process has continued with the sequential emergence of atoms,
molecules, complex chemistry, biology, neural-based behaviour and human culture
marking some of the major landmarks in this evolutionary history. Perhaps the
latter items only have an existence on our planet, perhaps there are further
emergent forms to be discovered in more remote areas of the universe. However,
there is good evidence that the earlier forms, those preceding biology, are
common to all corners of the universe.
Over the history of the universe a large number of complex
forms have progressively emerged into existence. It is evident that these forms
represent a hierarchy in which the more complex entail the less complex and
also that they emerged into existence in a sequential manner from the simple to
the more complex over time. A unified theory of existence would include a
detailed description of this evolutionary process.
There has been a number of recent theoretical advances in
evolutionary theory. Beginning with the research of Steven Frank it has been
made clear that the mathematics of Darwinian evolution are a form of Bayesian
inference [4, 5]. It has also been
demonstrated that processes described by the mathematics or Bayesian inference
may also be cast as theories based on the principle of variational free energy [6, 7]. More recently it
has been found that evolutionary theory based on the principle of variational
free energy may, in turn, be cast in terms of gauge theories [8].
A great advantage of viewing evolutionary theory in these
various theoretical frameworks is that different aspects are exposed.
Describing evolutionary processes in terms of Bayesian inference draws
attention to ‘learned’ fitness while descriptions in terms of free energy provide
a focus on internal models and the tendency of evolutionary processes to reduce
the prediction error of their models. Casting evolutionary theory in terms of gauge
theory draws attention to mechanisms which systems develop to maintain stability
or homeostasis.
Unfortunately, these theoretical frameworks have been
applied only to post-physical phenomena, those forms which have emerged from
the physical substrates including biology, neural based behaviour and culture.
The broad scope of scientific subject matter within the physical sciences has
not been brought within this framework. This is important as post-physical
phenomena evolved both later than and out of physical phenomena. A unified
theory would necessarily include purely physical phenomena.
The unifying theoretical framework of the physical sciences
is gauge theory which has been used to describe all physical forces. As gauge
theory also provides a unified framework for post-physical evolutionary
systems, its explanatory power in the physical sciences may hint at a unified
approach. To date however, it has not been demonstrated, to the satisfaction of
most researchers, that physical systems can be cast as evolutionary systems.
Three of the four physical forces are described within the
standard model of particle physics as quantum gauge theories. General relativity
is also a gauge theory and may be understood as an effect of quantum
entanglement [9].
Zurek’s development of quantum theory
Quantum theory is replete with interpretational issues but rapid
progress has been made during recent decades in understanding quantum
decoherence, the process by which information is exchanged by quantum systems.
Foremost in this advance has been the research of Wojciech Zurek and a small
group of colleagues.
Zurek has an illustrious scientific pedigree. His mentor and
close colleague for many years was John Archibald Wheeler. Wheeler had an
extraordinary ability to guide his associates to brilliant scientific
accomplishments. His graduate students include David Deutsch, Richard Feynman,
Hugh Everett and Jacob Bekenstein, some of the most creative physicists ever.
Within his field of quantum decoherence, Zurek is the acknowledged expert and
some, including a Scientific American blog, consider it likely he will
eventually be awarded the Nobel Prize [10].
Early in Zurek’s career he co-edited, with Wheeler, the
authoritative Quantum Theory and Measurement
(1983). This subject has remained
the focus of Zurek’s research, except that he has come to think in terms of
interactions instead of measurements. Quantum measurement is widely recognized
to present a problem which has plagued the theory since its inception known as
‘the measurement problem’. This problem is baked into quantum theory as it is
written into the axioms which underlie quantum theory. A common list of the
axioms is summarized [11]:
- States are represented by vectors in Hilbert space
- Evolutions are unitary (Schrödinger’s equation)
- Immediate repetition of a measurement yields the same outcome
- Outcomes correspond to eigenstates of the measured observable, and only one of them is detected in any given run of the experiment.
- Probability of a measurement outcome is given by the square of the associated amplitude, known as Born's rule.
The word ‘measurement’ is used in three of the axioms.
Axioms 4 and 5 describe measurement predictions and these suggest that upon
measurement the quantum system ‘jumps’ to a particular state but this appears
to be in contradiction with axiom 2 which describes the evolution of quantum
states as being continuous, that is, without jumps. Thus the ‘measurement
problem’. Less discussed but more troubling, the word ‘measurement’ has
suggested to many that human involvement is required for quantum interactions
to take place.
Fortunately, Zurek’s research program, extending over
thirty-five years, has largely rescued physics from this disorder. He has
simplified the axiomatic foundations of quantum theory [12, 11, 13], showing how the
problem axioms 4 and 5 are logically implied by the first three. In the process,
we see that the use of the word ‘measurement’ is misleading in its suggestion
that quantum interactions are dependent upon human actions.
Zurek’s revolution is to derive axiom 5 and most of axiom 4
from the first three axioms [14]. As axioms 4 and 5
constitute what has been known as the ‘measurement problem’ this derivation has
substantially resolved that problem as quantum ‘jumps’ are given a detailed
explanation and shown to be implied by the first three axioms and thus to be an
integral part of quantum theory.
His approach to quantum theory focuses upon the nature of
interactions which quantum systems have with entities in their environment and
the information exchange which takes place during these interactions. Prior to
information exchange the quantum system and the entity in its environment with
which it will interact become entangled. In this peculiar state of entanglement
both entities lose their individual identity and become instead a composite
entity described by a single wave function. As the information exchange is
completed they separate, or decohere, and again become individual entities but
now the quantum system is aligned with the information placed in the
environment. Quantum theory provides a probabilistic prediction of the exact
nature of the information which is transferred to the environment. Often the
prediction forms a probability distribution over possible outcomes where the
probability of any single outcome is less than 1.
Due to this process of decoherence the quantum system and
the information concerning it in the environment become synchronized in accord
with axiom 3. If the quantum system becomes immediately entangled again with
the same environmental entity it will exchange the same information as it did
the first time but this time with probability 1. This means that during the
first interaction the quantum system and the information transferred to the
environment were updated to have complete mutual information; if you know the
state of one of them you also know the state of the other. In the second interaction,
the quantum system is ‘pure’, it only contains the same information as that
transferred during the first interaction and is now constrained to transfer
that same information again.
We might note however that axiom 3 talks about this
interaction in terms of measurement, while Zurek describes it as decoherence or
information exchange. A great advantage of Zurek’s approach is that he
describes quantum interactions in general rather than the specific interactions
which take place when humans perform measurements. As Zurek explains, a
measurement is only one possible type of quantum interaction [13]:
Any
process of quantum measurement necessarily involves an interaction between two
or more systems. That this is true can be seen by considering that a
measurement, by definition, involves a transfer of information between systems: system S has been “measured” only if there exists another system E, that carries information about the state of S
With this subtle shift
decades of hubris requiring human involvement in quantum processes is swept
away. When information transfer between a quantum system and its environment is
examined, it turns out that the symmetries of entanglement imply that only an
extremely small subset of the information required to fully describe a quantum
system may be transferred to the environment and survive there in other than
minute quantities. Although it is limited, this information is all that other
entities may experience of the quantum system, it is the only aspects they can
know. Thus, this scanty information is all that exists of the quantum system in
the outside reality.
The information which
can survive and proliferate in the environment and exist in many redundant
copies is classical information and this is why we experience a classical
reality rather than a weird quantum reality. It is not only us who experiences
this; all entities, including fundamental particles such as electrons,
experience the same classical reality. Thus, we are rescued from being alien
beings who experience reality in a different manner from the rest of nature.
In Zurek’s paradigm, the
widely distributed classical information is the basis of our objective reality;
numerous observers, each examining a small fragment of the environment in the
vicinity of a quantum system, will find identical information regarding the
quantum system. This leads them to objectively agree on the details and thus
the existence of the quantum system. Such objectivity provides a ‘point of view
invariance’ confined not just to human observers but one experienced by all
entities.
Quantum Darwinism
Zurek has named his theory, by which many redundant copies
of classical information are selected from quantum information and are able to
survive in the environment, the theory of quantum Darwinism. Like other
Darwinian processes, quantum Darwinism follows the mathematics of Bayesian
inference [15], that is, it learns
or discovers through a process of trial and error those forms capable of an
existence.
The agency of Darwinian processes in quantum physics would
go a long way to providing a unified theory of existence. The fact that a
Darwinian theory has been posited at the basis of quantum physics by a leading
authority is intriguing but after more than a decade this theory remains
largely ignored and far from a consensus. However, as we will see below the
link it provides between fundamental physics and Darwinian processes may be
crucial.
The application of the Darwinian paradigm to processes in
basic physics is unusual but it may assist our search for a generalized
description of how simple entities evolve into more complex forms. Outside of
fundamental physics the Darwinian process is widely understood as the
evolutionary agent governing complex entities in biology, neuroscience and
culture [5]. Darwin’s theory of
natural selection, the initially understood Darwinian process, ultimately
describes the process by which new biological forms are brought into existence.
Biological forms enjoy an existence while they are reproductively successful,
those that are not reproductively successful cease to exist. The change in
frequency of biological traits over generations, which underlies natural
selection, is merely the change in frequency of those traits which exist. The
theory of universal Darwinism [5, 16,
17]
which generalizes natural selection to subject matters other than biology
retains this dependence on the changing frequency of traits which exist.
Gauge Theories
As we have seen evolutionary theory may be framed in numerous
mathematical forms. While the nature of these various forms is not important at
this stage, it is important to note that evolutionary theory may in general be
cast as gauge theories as this provides a common theoretical link to physical
phenomena.
Gauge theories are typified by an ability to provide, via
the gauge field, point of view invariance [18], that is the laws of
nature look the same to all observers despite their particular circumstances.
Gauge theories create this invariance by introducing a gauge field or force
which serves to act upon phenomena so that it retains a point of view
invariance. This is the basis of an objective reality; one where various
observers agree as to what they are observing.
One might wonder why the free energy principle or gauge
theory captures significant features of universal Darwinism. Why for example
should natural systems minimize their free energy or produce gauge fields to
maintain their homeostasis? The short answer is that only those complex systems
which act to minimize their free energy or maintain their homeostasis can exist [19].
The standard model of particle physics is another scientific
path to ‘point of view invariance’, or objectivity at the fundamental physical
level. This model is a virtuoso as it exactly accounts for all known
fundamental particles; all the particles it describes and only the particles it
describes have been experimentally verified.
In addition, it describes three forces through which the fundamental
particles may interact. The theories describing these forces take the form of gauge
theories. In addition, gravitational theory may also be formulated as a gauge
theory. Thus, the best theories of all four forces found in fundamental physics
are gauge theories.
Unification
We have arrived at the remarkable situation where all
evolutionary theories outside of physics as well as the four forces of
fundamental physics may be cast as gauge theories. If it were possible to
understand the gauge theories of fundament physics as evolutionary theories
then we would have approached the goal of a single theoretical framework that
explains evolutionary processes taking place in nature, it would provide
progress towards a unified theory of existence.
A direct route to this conclusion
would be provided if the theory of quantum Darwinism is confirmed. Darwinian
theories are Bayesian and therefore may be cast as gauge theories. If quantum
Darwinism proves true, then consistency requires that its formulation as a
gauge theory must be equivalent to the gauge theories of the standard model.
The gauge theories of the standard model describe four
particles called gauge bosons (five if we include the graviton). All
interactions between fundamental particles are mediated by the gauge bosons
which are said to carry the gauge field.
We may take gravity, described by the general theory of
relativity, as an example. The experience of an observer in free fall is
special, they do not experience a gravitational force. Accelerated observers,
those not in free fall, do experience a gravitational force. This gravitational
force serves to make the experience of the two observers compatible, it acts via
an exchange of gravitons to make the experience of observers equivalent; using
the theory of gravity all observers will make the same predictions.
We might note that quantum Darwinism provides an alternative
understanding to gauge theory of an objective ‘point of view invariance’; it
arises because only specific, consistent and redundant information that has
been selected by this Darwinian process is available to a large number of
observers. Observers of quantum systems may experience those systems only by
accessing the available information. All observers will experience the same
information and will thus agree on the objective nature of the system. Thus,
both gauge theories and quantum Darwinism account for the experience of ‘point
of view invariance’ within quantum phenomena, a necessary component of
objective existence. However, gauge theories appear conceptually quite
different from Darwinian theories. We must dig a little deeper to discover
their compatibility.
Friston and colleagues have shown that gauge theories may be
constructed from any theory based on variational free energy [8]. They also note that
many aspects of biology and neuroscience are describe by variational free
energy. Free energy is a measure of the discrepancy between an internal model
and the evidence it receives. The principle of variational free energy states
that systems will act to minimize the free energy or amount of error between
their internal model and the evidence they experience.
In biological systems, the internal model takes the form of
DNA and in neuroscience it takes the form of generative mental models. In
biology, for example, an organism’s genome is an internal model which contains
a strategy for survival or existence. The free energy principle predicts that
organisms will act to minimize errors in their strategy, that they will attempt
to survive by accurately and efficiently executing the strategy coded in their
genome.
An organism’s survival may be understood in terms of
homeostasis or the maintenance of an internal equilibrium in the face of
environmental fluctuations. Maintaining themselves in homeostasis allows the
organism to achieve the two main components of existence, persistence and
objectivity.
No organism can stray into states too far from its
programmed state of equilibrium and continue to exist. As in the Dawkins quote
there are far more ways of being dead than being alive and if an organism once
strays into a state of death there is no coming back. An organism’s survival
and existence depends on its ability to perform its programmed strategy for
homeostasis.
When these theories, cast in terms of free energy, are
transformed to gauge theories, the actions or behaviours which an entity may
employ to maintain homeostasis may be considered gauge fields. They are forces
which the entity can employ to maintain itself within existence.
Within physical gauge theories, gauge fields take the form
of gauge bosons, such as photons, particles capable of transferring information
between fundamental particles. It is the information carried by gauge bosons
which allows systems of fundamental particles to appear invariant to local
transformations, that is to achieve homeostasis. This information transfer is a
quantum interaction and provides the fundamental means by which one entity may
gain information of another. As discussed above an entity that in incapable of
providing information of itself to other entities cannot be said to exist. Thus,
it is also the case with physical gauge theories that the gauge field maintains
entities within existence.
Quantum Darwinism also describes the interactions mediated
by gauge bosons but has a focus on the transfer of information that these carry
between a quantum system and entities in its environment. It describes this
information transfer as a Darwinian process, one where many possible forms are
attempted but only a few are selected for their ability to survive and
reproduce, where only a few forms can achieve homeostasis and objective
existence. During an interview at Perimeter Institute Zurek explained [20]:
It
turns out in quantum mechanics you can understand the emergence of things which
are stable and therefore are candidates for things that are classical using
essentially Darwin’s idea. First of all they should be stable in spite of what
the environment is trying to do to them …. So that information about the stable
states gets multiplied, proliferates, stable states spawn information theoretic
copies all over the place, so this is the proliferation of the species, a la
Darwin.
Naming his theory quantum Darwinism is a tribute to Zurek’s
intellectual breadth and his ability to recognize analogies across the scope of
scientific understanding. It is also a testament to his courage as it has not
been popular amongst physicists. Physicist have traditionally viewed themselves
as the preeminent scientists whose standards set a very high bar for other
fields. Rutherford famously typified biology as ‘stamp collecting’ and Darwin’s
most challenging contemporary critic was Lord Kelvin who incorrectly claimed to
have demonstrated the impossibility of natural selection.
The reaction of many physicists to Zurek’s placement of
biology’s most central theory at the foundations of physical theory has been to
ignore it. Despite its great theoretical advance and support from empirical
evidence, Zurek’s biological analogy has largely been shunned.
Physicists preferred theory of fundamental interactions,
Gauge theory, describes quantum interactions as the interaction between a gauge
field and a particle. Quantum Darwinism tells us that another way of viewing this
interaction is as a Darwinian process. In this view the classical information
describing quantum systems which exists and is available in the systems’ environments
are adaptive forms; they have been selected by a Darwinian process for their
ability to survive and reproduce. This identification of physical gauge fields
as adaptations provides a crucial link between physical and post-physical gauge
theories.
Scientific understanding of the history of the universe
since its beginning in the big bang reveals an evolutionary history. In the
very beginning there was only massless radiation. More complex fundamental
particles including those having mass emerged in sequence from simple to more
complex. This process has continued with the sequential emergence of atoms,
molecules, complex chemistry, biology, neural-based behaviour and human culture
marking some of the major landmarks. Perhaps the latter items only have an
existence on our planet, perhaps there are further emergent forms to be
discovered in more remote areas of the universe. However, there is good
evidence that the earlier forms, those preceding biology, are common to all
corners of the universe.
Over the history of the universe a large number of complex
forms have progressively emerged into existence. We may now be on the verge of
being able to describe, at least those forms which have emerged in our
neighborhood, in terms of a single theoretical framework: gauge theory. It is
evident that these forms represent a hierarchy in which the more complex entail
the less complex and also that they emerged into existence in a sequential
manner from the simple to the more complex over time.
A unified theory of existence should include a detailed
description of this evolutionary process. Again, given that physical gauge
theories may be equivalent to quantum Darwinism and post-physical gauge
theories may be equivalent to a formulation in terms of the free energy
principle, gauge theories may be capable of explaining this evolutionary
process. To see how this could work we can first examine the approach taken by
Karl Friston and colleagues. His research considers self-organising systems,
those systems that have emerged through post-physical evolutionary processes [8]:
The
basic idea is that any self-organising system, at nonequilibrium steady-state
with its environment, will appear to minimise its (variational) free energy,
thus resisting a natural tendency to disorder. This formulation reduces the
physiology of biological systems to their homeostasis (and allostasis); namely,
the maintenance of their states and form, in the face of a constantly changing
environment.
Self-organising systems capable of regulating themselves
within homeostatic bounds must contain an internal model which details the
required regulation [21]. The system’s
challenge is to maintain itself in a state close to that prescribed by its
model. This can be viewed as minimizing the error of its model or the surprise
experienced by the system. Mathematically this reduction of surprise is bounded
by the free energy of the system so the efforts employed by a self-organizing
system to maintain its homeostasis may be described mathematically as the
minimization of free energy. Friston has proposed this free energy principle as
a unifying principle in biology and neuroscience [19].
Nature has many means of winnowing phenomena out of
existence which may be summarized as the second law of thermodynamics. It is
well known that the adaptations which allow organisms to resist these forces
towards disorder have evolved through the Darwinian process of natural
selection and it has been shown that the Bayesian mathematics describing
Darwinian processes are equivalent to a formulation in terms of the free energy
principle [5]. Friston and
colleagues have recently proposed that the resistance to disorder employed by
complex systems may also be formulated in terms of gauge theory [8]:
If
the minimisation of variational free energy is a ubiquitous aspect of
biological systems, could it be the Lagrangian of a gauge theory? This (free
energy) Lagrangian has proved useful in understanding many aspects of
functional brain architectures; for example, its hierarchical organisation and
the asymmetries between forward and backward connections in cortical
hierarchies. In this setting, the system stands for the brain (with neuronal or
internal states), while the environment (with external states) is equipped with
continuous forces and produces local sensory perturbations that are countered
through action and perception (that are functionals of the gauge field).
In a gauge theory, it is the gauge field which is
responsible for countering local asymmetries or fluctuations and maintaining
homeostasis. Biological theory understands that it is adaptations, evolved
through Darwinian processes, which serve to achieve homeostasis. This suggests that gauge fields, in
post-physical gauge theories, may also be interpreted as adaptations brought
into existence by Darwinian processes which in turn suggests a unified
interpretation among gauge theories of homeostasis maintained by the actions of
adaptations brought into existence through Darwinian processes.
Perhaps the biggest
challenge in the development of physical gauge theories was the process of
renormalization by which finite predictions concerning the state of a system
can be made. The main
idea of renormalization is to correct the original Lagrangian of a gauge theory
by a series of counterterms. If the minimization of free energy may be the
Lagrangian of a post physical gauge theory, as suggested by Friston et. al,
then the renormalization of this theory would perhaps involve the adding up of
the counter terms provided by the gauge field, in this case the sum of the
system’s adaptations. The sum of the adaptations may act to maintain homeostasis
and allow existence.
Explaining the evolutionary transitions to a new, more
complex, hierarchical form is a greater challenge for evolutionary theory than
explaining the maintenance of homeostasis within an existing form. For example,
a detailed explanation of the evolution of chemistry to life has eluded
researchers for decades. Recent research indicates that this may finally be
within our grasp. Scientists at The Scripps Research Institute have constructed
a ribozyme from chemical building blocks that can basically serve both to
amplify genetic information and to generate functional molecules. In the
opinion of some experts, the one remaining barrier between this chemistry and
life is to have the ribozyme make copies of itself. As the lead author, Gerald
Joyce, explains [22]:
“A
polymerase ribozyme that achieves exponential amplification of itself will meet
the criteria for being alive,” Joyce said. “That’s a summit that’s now within
sight.”
Researchers are now working feverishly to accomplish this
last step.
Perhaps for our purposes it is more important to understand
how life might be discovered or selected from the multitude of possible
chemical reactions and established within existence as a new self-organizing
system. The technique used by Joyce’s team in their discovery is called in vitro evolution or directed
evolution. This is a Darwinian process developed by chemists for the discovery
of new chemical forms. Basically, the process starts with a first generation of
potential molecules having some variations amongst them, then these molecules
are tested for the desired chemical qualities and a relatively small number
which have qualities closest to the goal are retained. In the next generation,
many copies of the retained molecules are made having small random variations
and the process is repeated. The long sought discovery of Joyce’s ribozyme was
accomplished in the 24th generation.
If it proves possible to go the next step and create a life
form, it will demonstrate that this Darwinian process is a method capable of
creating complex systems which are themselves subject to evolution. It seems
likely that nature accomplished the initial transition from chemistry to life
using a similar method. We might note that in this view the Darwinian process
is a constant over time. It operates in the realm of chemistry, per the
principles of quantum Darwinism, discovering and retaining complex forms
capable of existence and when it accomplishes the transition to life this
transition is typified by a new type of Darwinian process, natural selection,
which continues to discover and retain further complex forms capable of
existence.
We may understand systems, such as the one created by
Joyce’s team, both as adaptations selected by a Darwinian process and as gauge
fields capable of maintaining homeostasis in a new complex system. This may
again suggest the view that gauge fields can be considered evolutionary agents
capable of bringing new complex systems into existence.
This essay has argued that much
of the phenomena studied by science may be described using gauge theories and
that the gauge fields of these theories may be typified as adaptations which
have evolved through Darwinian processes. In this view Darwinian processes are
responsible both for bringing new phenomena into existence and for maintaining
systems within existence. This approach may go some way towards developing a
unified theory of existence.
References
[1]
|
R. Dawkins, The
Blind Watchmaker, Norton & Company, Inc, 1986.
|
[2]
|
J. K. Sherrif,
Charles Peirce's Guess at the Riddle: Grounds for Human Significance,
Indiana University Press, 1994.
|
[3]
|
Wikipedia,
"Existence," [Online]. Available: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Existence.
[Accessed 14 8 2016].
|
[4]
|
S. A. Frank,
"Natural selection. V. How to read the fundamental equations of
evolutionary change in terms of information theory," Journal of
Evolutionary Biology, Vols. 25:2377-2396., 2012.
|
[5]
|
J. O. Campbell,
"Universal Darwinism as a process of Bayesian inference," System
Neuroscience, 2016.
|
[6]
|
S. Roweis and Z.
Ghahramani, "A unifying view of linear Gaussian models," Neural
Computation, vol. 11 , no. 2.
|
[7]
|
K. Friston,
"The free energy principle: a unified brain theory?," Nature
Reviews Neuroscience , vol. 11, pp. 127-138|, 2010.
|
[8]
|
B. Sengupta, A.
Tozzi , G. . K. Cooray, P. K. Douglas and K. J. Friston, "Towards a
Neuronal Gauge Theory," PLOS Biology, vol. 14(3): e1002400.,
2016.
|
[9]
|
M. Van Raamsdonk, Lectures
on Gravity and Entanglement, Arxiv preprint, 2016.
|
[10]
|
J. Ouellette,
"Nobel Crystal Ball: Predictions for the 2014 Prize in Physics,"
3 October 2014. [Online]. Available: http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/cocktail-party-physics/2014/10/03/nobel-crystal-ball-predictions-for-2014-prize-in-physics/.
[Accessed 12 December 2014].
|
[11]
|
W. H. Zurek,
"Quantum Darwinism," Nature Physics, vol. 5, pp. 181-188,
2009.
|
[12]
|
W. H. Zurek,
"Pointer basis of quantum apparatus: Into what mixture does the wave
packet collapse?," Physical Review, 1981.
|
[13]
|
J. Harris, F.
Bouchard, E. Santamato, W. H. Zurek, R. W. Boyd and E. Karimi,
"Quantum probabilities from quantum entanglement: experimentally
unpacking the Born rule," New Journal of Physics, vol. 18, no.
5, 2016.
|
[14]
|
W. H. Zurek,
"Quantum Darwinism, Classical Reality, and the randomness of quantum
jumps.," Physics Today, Vols. vol. 67, pp. 44-50 (2014), 2014.
|
[15]
|
J. O. Campbell,
"Quantum Darwinism as a Darwinian process," Arxiv Preprint, 2010.
|
[16]
|
J. O. Campbell,
Universal Darwinism: The path of knowledge, CreateSpace, 2011.
|
[17]
|
J. O. Campbell,
Darwin Does Physics, createspace, 2014.
|
[18]
|
V. J. Stenger, The
comprehensible cosmos: where do the laws of physics come from?, Prometheus
Books, 2006.
|
[19]
|
K. Friston,
"Life as we know it," J R Soc Interface, vol. 10:
20130475, 3 July 2013.
|
[20]
|
W. Zurek,
Interviewee, Quantum Darwinism - Dr. Wojciech Zurek. [Interview]. 27
June 2012.
|
[21]
|
R. Conant and R.
Ashby, "Every good regulator of a system must be a model of that
system," Int. J. Systems Sci., p. 89–97, 1970.
|
[22]
|
The Scripts
Research Institue, "TSRI Scientists Take Big Step Toward Recreating
Primordial ‘RNA World’ of Four Billion Years Ago," 15 August 2016.
[Online]. Available:
https://www.scripps.edu/news/press/2016/20160815joyce.html.
|
No comments:
Post a Comment