John O. Campbell
May 2017
May 2017
Carlo Rovelli’s proposal for basing a
relational quantum mechanics on a set of information theoretic postulates (1) appears to have recently
been realized in the research of Phillipp Hoehn (2). This program holds great promise and after
eighty years of misconception we may finally be making a start in formulating a
comprehensible interpretation of quantum theory.
Rovelli's initial sketch of a relational
quantum theory was posted as a preprint in 1994 (3) and has since been
updated, most recently in 1997. Although much of his subsequent research has
focused on other topics, he has further developed his views on relational
quantum theory in two subsequent papers (4; 5).
It is remarkable that in the conclusion of
his 1997 outline of relational quantum theory he writes that it had just come
to his attention that Wojciech Zurek’s had precedence (1982) in developing ‘conclusions that are identical to the ones
developed here.’ (1) . Although Rovelli
acknowledges that Zurek arrived at these conclusions fifteen years earlier, he
does not mention, in this or his subsequent papers, Zurek’s on-going research
program advancing the subject. We might well pay close attention to Zurek’s
research not only because he had a fifteen-year head start on Rovelli but also
because he has focused on the development of this topic throughout his career
and has published dozens of papers on the subject.
Hoehn claims that his axiomatic formulation
of quantum theory supports Rovelli’s interpretation and that Hoehn’s ‘successful reconstruction can be viewed as
a completion of these ideas for qubit systems’ (2). Neither Hoehn’s nor Rovelli’s
subsequent papers mention or cite Zurek’s research.
Hoehn’s development of quantum theory is
most instructive as it is in terms of information theory. Hoehn considers an
observer who entails a probabilistic model of the state of some phenomena and
is able to ask questions and receive answers regarding the phenomena. He
specifies some constraints on the model: the questions and the answers in the
form of 5 rules or postulates. The answers are used to update the probabilistic
state model according to the principles of Bayesian inference and in this
manner the observer’s model becomes a ‘catalogue of knowledge’ regarding the
observed phenomena.
Importantly, the observer, its questions,
answers and the Bayesian process used to update its model form a system that
will accumulate evidence-based knowledge. I have used the term ‘inferential
systems’ (6; 7) to describe similar
systems that operate to accumulate knowledge in non-quantum or classical
reality. The Rovelli/Hoehn (RH) paradigm posits this same mechanism at the
basis of quantum theory and thus suggests that inferential systems may be a
unifying paradigm across the entire scope of reality. This suggestion is
important because it removes quantum phenomena from the ‘weird’ interpretations
traditionally applied to it and instead places it firmly within the same
paradigm that is used to describe many other natural systems.
As Hoehn demonstrates, the model, or
‘catalogue of knowledge’ which the observer will evolve by following the
postulates is quantum theory itself. In other words, the model that the
observer will infer to describe and predict the phenomena under consideration
is quantum theory.
Hoehn thereby demonstrates that quantum
theory is the logical product of an inferential system which processes
information in a manner consistent with his postulates. Rovelli stresses that
the ‘observer’ in this paradigm may be any physical object (1) and hence provides
an explanation for the universal applicability of quantum theory. It is most
natural to place the observer at the level of the quantum system itself. All
quantum systems are associated with a state function which receives and
processes information. The HR paradigm explains why this state function is
quantum mechanical and thus offers an explanation for quantum mechanics:
quantum mechanics is the body of knowledge which any system will infer when
constrained to exchange and process information in accord with Hoehn’s
postulates.
The startling conclusion is that reality at
the micro level may be described by quantum theory because its information
acquisition and processing is constrained in accord with Hoehn’s postulates.
Zurek’s 1982 paper which contains ‘conclusions that are identical to the ones
developed’ in Rovelli’s 1997 paper, came near the beginnings of Zurek’s
research program into decoherence or the nature of quantum interactions. Through
this research Zurek attempts to answer a central question posed by quantum
theory: why do we never experience weird quantum phenomena such as
superpositions as described by theory, why do we instead experience definite
classical outcomes? The answer he provides is described on his FQXi page (8):
Zurek hopes that the answer may lie at the intersection of three
well-developed ideas in quantum theory. The first is decoherence, a theory Zurek has been instrumental in advancing
since 1981. Decoherence describes what happens when a system in superposition
interacts with its environment: It becomes entangled with particles in the
outside world that record its location, causing the superposition to fall apart
(decohere) into a probabilistic mixture of definite states at specific
locations. Only systems in perfect isolation can remain in superposition. A
single errant photon can destroy the superposition, like the faintest breeze
knocking down a house of cards.
Decoherence explains how familiar, classical physics emerges from the haze of quantum mechanics, and clears up vexing paradoxes like that of Schrödinger’s famous cat, locked in a box with a poisonous substance that will be released if a radioactive atom decays. While the box is closed, the usual story goes, the radioactive atom is in a superposition state in which it has both decayed and not decayed, leaving the trapped cat in limbo too. Decoherence helps resolve this, however: We don’t need to worry about the cat being alive and dead at once because a macroscopic feline can’t maintain the perfect isolation required to hold the superposition.
Decoherence explains how familiar, classical physics emerges from the haze of quantum mechanics, and clears up vexing paradoxes like that of Schrödinger’s famous cat, locked in a box with a poisonous substance that will be released if a radioactive atom decays. While the box is closed, the usual story goes, the radioactive atom is in a superposition state in which it has both decayed and not decayed, leaving the trapped cat in limbo too. Decoherence helps resolve this, however: We don’t need to worry about the cat being alive and dead at once because a macroscopic feline can’t maintain the perfect isolation required to hold the superposition.
Zurek has derived his research results starting
from the traditional quantum axioms of the Copenhagen interpretation. In the process,
he has reduced the number of required axioms and has largely eliminate the
problematic axioms which lead to the ‘measurement problem’ that has plagued
quantum theory since its inception. However, as Hoehn’s set of axioms
describing an inferential system is an equivalent starting point for the
derivation of quantum theory, Zurek could have equally well performed his
research starting from Hoehn’s and Rovelli’s framework.
This, as we will see, has some important
advantages as Zurek’s more recent research has led him to conclusions that
resonate very well with Rovelli’s interpretation. In the meantime Zurek’s
research program has moved beyond decoherence (8).
But decoherence does not explain why all observers share the same
classical reality—that is, why reality is objective rather than subjective. For
that, Zurek turns to the second piece of the puzzle, the theory of quantum
Darwinism, which Zurek and his colleagues and collaborators have been
developing over the past dozen years. Quantum Darwinism specifies how the
environment selects and disseminates information about favored states. These
favored states emerge through a process dubbed "einselection," or environment
induced
superselection,
and are recorded and copied by the environment during decoherence. "This
proliferation of "copies" of the states allows many observers to find
out independently about the system, without disturbing it by
measurements—hence, without getting in each others’ way," explains Zurek.
"This consensus defines "objectivity" of the classical everyday
reality."
To be clear, Zurek has named this theory
‘Quantum Darwinism’ not out of whimsy but rather because he considers the
process he is describing as a true Darwinian process (9):
In the end one might ask: “How Darwinian is Quantum Darwinism?”
Clearly, there is survival of the fittest, and fitness is defined as in natural
selection.
Zurek’s understanding of quantum systems
focuses on the environment surrounding the quantum system, an environment which
is itself composed of quantum systems, and the information which those systems forming
the environment may share with a particular quantum system that they ‘witness’.
He has found that most of the information necessary to fully describe a quantum
system is not able to survive in its environment. Only a very small subset of the
‘fittest’ information can survive and proliferate leaving many redundant
copies. This subset of information is ‘classical’ or Holevo information as
distinct from purely quantum information known as ‘quantum discord’. Thus, most
of the information which fully describes the state of a quantum system cannot
be communicated to any other entity or observer (10; 11).
The small subset of information which can survive the transfer and be
communicated to other entities forms the basis of objective classical reality.
Observers seeking information regarding the
quantum system may sample the environment and each observer will find the same
information leading to their experience of an objective, classical reality. We
should remember that it is common for observers to gather information
concerning a quantum system by sampling its environment. For example,
everything we ‘see’ is the result of photons in the environment of the quantum
system. At a basic level, as classical information is the only information
which may be communicated, it is this information that forms an objective
classical reality and Zurek characterizes this process as the emergence of
classical reality from its quantum substrate.
The name ‘quantum Darwinism’ is descriptive
as classical reality is composed from the fittest information, in relation to
its environment, the information which can survive and proliferate.
Zurek’s and HR’s paradigms describe quantum
systems from two separate viewpoints. Zurek maintains a focus on the
environment surrounding the quantum system and the information describing the
quantum system which may be transferred to this environment. He describes this
process as a Darwinian process in the sense that only ‘fit’ quantum information
can survive in its environment just as in biology where only ‘fit’ genetic
information may survive in its environment. Fit genetic information is capable
of constructing reproductively successful phenotypes, fit quantum information
is capable of constructing reproductively successful classical phenomena. In
the quantum case the selection of fit information results in the existence of
classical reality in the biological case the selection of fit information
results in the existence of the biosphere.
On the other hand, HR maintain an ‘outward facing’
focus on the quantum system itself and the information it may contain describing
the other quantum systems composing its environment. Through an inferential
procedure detailed in the postulates, the quantum system elicits, receives and
processes information and as a result infers a quantum worldview or, in HR
terms, a quantum catalogue of knowledge.
It may appear that although HR and Zurek
once shared a common view that this has diverged significantly since. How can
we reconcile their apparent divergent focuses on the interior and exterior
aspects of quantum systems? The answer may lie in the ‘repeatability’ postulate
of quantum theory: an immediately
repeated measurement yields the same outcome. Although the measured outcome may
have initially been predicted by the quantum state with a probability less than
one, following the initial measurement the quantum state becomes homologous with
the outcome so that a repeated measurement is predicted to produce the same
outcome with probability 1. The interior quantum system becomes homologous with
the information regarding it that is recorded in the environment. The interior
and exterior views are synchronized so that interior and exterior descriptions are
equivalent.
Even given this
equivalency how can we reconcile the interior description in terms of an
inferential process with the exterior description in terms of a Darwinian
process? Recent results show this to be straight forward; the mathematics of
Darwinian processes are the mathematics of Bayesian inference. The ‘relative
fitness’ of a Darwinian description is the likelihood of a Bayesian
description.
For example, the
Darwinian change in the frequency of biological alleles between generations has
long been described by population biologists as (12):
where ‘p’ is the probability of the
particular allele in the latter generation, p
is the probability of the particular allele in the former generation, RA
is the fitness of the particular allele and is the average fitness of all competing
alleles. This equation describes a Bayesian update where the frequency in the
previous generation is updated by the ratio of two other probabilities, the
ratio of the fitness of the particular allele to the average fitness of all
alleles for that characteristic.
The Price equation,
which is the mathematics of generalized Darwinian processes, has been shown to
be equivalent to the mathematics of Bayesian inference and so we might
understand Darwinian processes as physically instantiated instances of Bayesian
inference (13; 6). In the quantum
realm, for example, we may understand Zurek’s quantum Darwinism as equivalent
to the inferential process described by HR.
This may be considered as a conceptual
breakthrough because inferential systems are found throughout nature wherever
knowledge is accumulated. Specifically, knowledge stores or ‘catalogues’ are
accumulated via inferential systems in biology, neural based behaviour and
culture (6; 7). Equivalently, in
each instance, these accumulations of knowledge evolve through a Darwinian
process. The inclusion of quantum theory within this framework hints at a truly
universal mechanism at the root of existence.
References
1. Relational Quantum Mechanics.
Rovelli, Carlo. s.l. : International Journal of Theoretical
Physics, 1996, Vols. 35 (1996) pp. 1637-78.
2. Quantum
theory from rules on information acquisition. Hoehn, Philipp Andres.
s.l. : Entropy, 2017, Vols. 19(3), 98;.
3. Wikipedia.
Relational quantum mechanics. Wikipedia. [Online] [Cited: 5 24, 2017.]
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Relational_quantum_mechanics.
4. Relative
information at the foundation of physics. Rovelli, Carlo.
s.l. : ArXiv preprint:1311.0054, 2013.
5. Meaning
= Information + Evolution. Rovelli, Carlo. s.l. :
arXiv:1611.02420 [physics.hist-ph], 2016.
6. Universal
Darwinism as a process of Bayesian inference. Campbell, John O.
s.l. : Front. Syst. Neurosci., 2016, System Neuroscience. doi:
10.3389/fnsys.2016.00049.
7. Campbell,
John O. Einstein's Enlightenment. s.l. : Createspace, 2017.
ASIN: B06XNZDGCS.
8. Becker,
Kate. Realities NeverEnding Story. FQXi Community. [Online] April
17, 2014. http://fqxi.org/community/articles/display/189.
9. Quantum
Darwinism. Zurek, Wojciech H. s.l. :
http://www.nature.com/nphys/journal/v5/n3/abs/nphys1202.html, 2009, Nature
Physics, vol. 5, pp. 181-188.
10. Complementarity
of quantum discord and classically accessible information. Zurek,
Wojciech and Zwolak, Michael. s.l. : Scientific Reports 3, Article
number: 1729, 2013. doi:10.1038/srep01729.
11. Quantum
discord cannot be shared. Streltsov, Alexander and Zurek, Wojciech.
4, s.l. : American Physical Society - Physical review letters, 2013,
Vol. 111.
12. Ricklefs,
Robert E. Ecology. Concord, Massachusetts : Chiron Press,
1979. p. 448.
13. Natural
selection. V. How to read the fundamental equations of evolutionary change in
terms of information theory. Frank, Steven, A. 2012, Journal of
Evolutionary Biology, Vols. 25:2377-2396.
No comments:
Post a Comment