John O. Campbell
This is an edited excerpt from the book Darwin Does Physics.
Many quantum mysteries have recently been understood by including
the effects of the quantum system’s environment as an integral part of
explanations of its behaviour. That prior explanations, which attempted to treat
quantum systems as isolated entities, led to a theory which, as Feynman
famously noted, nobody understood is hardly surprising, We can only imagine how
ridiculous a theory of biology would be that tried to described the multitude
of adaptations displayed by organisms without references to their environments.
A 2014 review article
by Maximilian Schlosshauer
describes the historical unfolding of this breakthrough in quantum understanding (1):
It is a curious “historical accident" that the role of the environment in quantum mechanics was appreciated only relatively late. While one can find -for example, in Heisenberg's writings – a few early anticipatory remarks about the role of environmental interactions in the quantum-mechanical description of systems, it wasn't until the 1970s that the ubiquity and implications of environmental entanglement were realized by Zeh. It took another decade for the formalism of decoherence to be developed, chiefly by Zurek
Wojciech Zurek is widely recognized as a leader in our
understanding of the nature of quantum interactions between a quantum system
and its environment or of quantum decoherence. Zurek’s progress in developing
his theory of quantum interactions may be broken into three steps centered on
three new concepts:
1) Einselection describes the type of information which may be transferred between a quantum system and in its environment during a quantum interaction. Zurek demonstrated that only information in the form of the system’s ‘pointer states’ can survive transfer to the environment. These pointer states depend upon both the nature of the system and the component of its environment with which it will share information. Pointer states describe the few classical characteristics, such as the systems position or momentum, which is all that the environment can experience of the quantum system
2) Envariance assigns a probability to each of the possible packets of information which may be transferred. These packets correlate with measurement values and thus envariance may be use to predict the outcome of possible measurements. It is of interest that Zurek derived these probabilistic predictions from fundamental quantum axioms rather than following the tradition of including them as a separate axiom.
3) Quantum Darwinism describes the relative reproductive success which the different various transferred information packet achieve in their environments. Zurek has shown that it is the classical information described by einselection and envariance that achieves a high level of redundancy in the environment; other types of information have a low survival rate. Zurek considers that the high level of redundancy of classical information provides classical reality with its objective nature; numerous observers will agree on the nature of reality as they have access only to a common and highly redundant but limited pool of information.
Together these concepts describe quantum interactions in
terms of a Darwinian process and I will refer to all three as the process of
quantum Darwinism. In each generation of information transfer just a small
subset of information is able to survive and reproduce in its environment. This
is deeply analogous to natural selection where in each generation of genetic
information transfer just a small subset of the possibilities are able to
survive and reproduce in their environments.
Figure 1: Wojciech Zurek
It is perhaps shocking to many physicists that the central
organizing principle of biology has been used to explain one of the most
fundamental physical processes. Although Zurek’s technical description has been
endorsed within consensus physics, its Darwinian implications have been shunned.
If you Google ‘quantum Darwinism’ and ignore entries written by him or myself,
you will be left with only meager comment. Zurek however is unequivocal
concerning the Darwinian nature of his theory (2):
The aim of this paper is to show that the emergence of the classical reality can be viewed as a result of the emergence of the preferred states from within the quantum substrate thorough the Darwinian paradigm, once the survival of the fittest quantum states and selective proliferation of the information about them are properly taken into account.
In my view this conjunction of fundamental physical and
biological explanations provides great hope for the unification of scientific
understanding within a few overarching concepts such as universal Darwinism.
Quantum Darwinism provides a detailed description of a
Darwinian process in terms of a single cycle, the evolution which occurs during a
single generation. While the shift in probabilities between two generations may
be the unit of evolutionary change it is the long term effects due to numerous
repetitions of this cycle which produce the dramatic accomplishments of
evolutionary systems.
To date the development of the theory of quantum Darwinism
has focused on processes involved in a single cycle and has not yet paid much
attention to the long term consequences produced by continual iterations over
cosmic time. We should be careful to understand that generational succession in
quantum Darwinism refers to the same phenotype, such as an atom, only at a
later time and possibly under slightly different circumstances. In this regards
it may be analogous to generations of single-celled asexual life where
succeeding generations are not truly new individuals but may rather be
considered as variations on the same individual with perhaps small changes in
circumstance.
In a number of earlier sections I have repeated Zurek’s
claim that ‘classical reality emerges from the quantum substrate’ but have not
provided much explanation for that astounding assertion. The claim itself may
seem somewhat metaphysical, as if classical reality arises as a kind of
ephemeral vapor from a more fundamental quantum reality. With a better
understanding of the mechanisms of quantum Darwinism, we are now prepared to
discuss this dramatic claim.
We might view the quantum substrate as a vast sea of quantum
systems which can interact with each other only by way of the four fundamental
forces – make that three if gravity is considered emergent from quantum forces.
As each system can only receive information concerning any other system by way
of these few forces, severe constraints are placed on the information which can
be received. Zurek understands these constraints as a Darwinian selection
mechanism which he describes within the theory of quantum Darwinism. ‘Classical’
information best survives the transfer to other quantum systems. Thus the
information that one system may acquire of another is largely classical
information.
We should understand that this information is physical, it
describes the only forces known to operate in the universe. Although these are
quantum forces they are well described by Newton’s classical mechanics because
the classical information, even though it describes only a small subset of the
quantum substrate is all that is available, all that passes through the
Darwinian selection mechanism. This information obeys classical logic and the
mathematics of probability theory which we consider forms of common sense. It
is insufficient to fully describe the quantum reality; that really is weird and
seems to operate as described by other forms of mathematics that do not jibe
with common sense.
Crucially, the information which can survive the transfer
entails all that one entity can feel, understand or react to concerning another
entity. In other words the ability of any entity to detect the outside world is
largely restricted to the classical characteristics of that world. Thus
classical reality emerges from the quantum substrate.
Both the logic we are familiar with and the physical nature
of our reality are explained as due to a Darwinian selection mechanism which
regulates the flow of information between entities. The universe is not static.
On the reception of information entities often react with an acceleration,
broadly as described by the classical theories of Newtonian mechanics,
Maxwell’s electro-magnetism and the theories of special and general
relativity. These are the forces and
logic which defines our classical reality. They are also the forces which
powered the evolution of the universe from the Big Bang onward.
Zurek’s theory implies that this evolution should be
understood as the operation of a Darwinian process. Each generation of
information exchanged by quantum systems is selected on the basis of its
reproductive success and earlier physical forms are distinguished from later
ones by their relative ability to survive and reproduce. In this view we can
understand the evolution of the universe since the Big Bang as a form of
Darwinian evolution.
From the beginning the great power of natural selection was
seen not so much in changes over a single generation, but rather in the
cumulative effect of these changes over evolutionary history. Already in On
the Origin of Species Darwin made the case that the many biological forms
found in nature have evolved from a single ancestral individual through the
process of natural selection. We might say that over evolutionary time genomes
have successively probed the huge number of environmental circumstance in which
they have found themselves for strategies of reproductive success and that new
phenotypes have been successively constructed to fit those circumstances.
Zurek has described decoherence and quantum Darwinism as
responsible for the transition from quantum to classical realities. In short
classical reality is composed of an extremely small subset of quantum
possibilities which are selected through a Darwinian process. In this view we
must see the evolution of classical reality as originating in this same
Darwinian process. Thus the history of the universe may be considered as shaped
through the operation of quantum Darwinism.
In Zurek’s terminology ‘pointer states’ are those quantum
states which may exist in classical reality. As he explains these states are
defined by their ability to achieve reproductive success within their
environments (3):
According to decoherence theory, the ability to withstand scrutiny of the environment defines pointer states. As I will discuss, the proliferation of records about those states throughout the environment is the essence of quantum Darwinism.
We often assume the physical evolution of the universe since
the Big Bang to be a rather straight forward case of cause and effect; the continued
expansion and cooling of the universe resulted in new forms and phenomena. The
Wikipedia article on the Chronology of the Universe (4) provides many examples of this way of
thinking including:
In the second phase, this quark–gluon plasma universe then cooled further, the current fundamental forces we know take their present forms through further symmetry breaking – notably the breaking of electroweak symmetry – and the full range of complex and composite particles we see around us today became possible, leading to a gravitationally dominated universe, the first neutral atoms (~ 80% hydrogen), and the cosmic microwave background radiation we can detect today.
Zurek’s theory suggests that this historical process may
have been more nuanced. New physical forms may have emerged as the universe changed
due to their ability to discover new environmental niches in which they could survive.
Within the scope of this theory we find a close analogy to
natural selection. We might say that over evolutionary time quantum systems
have successively probed the huge number of environmental circumstance in which
they have found themselves for strategies of reproductive success and that new
phenotypes have been successively constructed to fit those circumstances. If we
understand ‘phenotype’, in this context, as the succession of physical forms,
the physical evolution of the universe since the Big Bang may be understood in
terms of a Darwinian process: Quantum Darwinism.
Bibliography
1. Schlosshauer,
Maximilian. The quantum-to-classical transition and decoherence. [book
auth.] M. Aspelmeyer, et al. Handbook of Quantum Information. 2014.
2. Zurek, Wojciech H. Quantum Darwinism and
envariance. [book auth.] P. C. W. Davies, and C. H. Harper, eds. J. D.
Barrow. Science and Ultimate Reality: From the Quantum to the Cosmos. s.l. :
Cambridge University Press, 2004.
3. Quantum Darwinism, Classical Reality, and the
randomness of quantum jumps. Zurek, Wojciech H. 2014, Physics
Today, Vols. vol. 67, pp. 44-50 (2014).
4. Wikipedia. Chronology of the Universe. Wikipedia.
[Online] [Cited: June 28, 2015.]
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Chronology_of_the_universe.